The lack of structure of knowledge
DOI:
https://doi.org/10.18012/arf.2016.41957Keywords:
Analysis of knowledge, Psychology of concepts, MindreadingAbstract
For a long time philosophers have struggled to reach a definition of knowledge that is fully satisfactory from an intuitive standard. However, what could be so fuzzy about the concept of knowledge that it makes our intuitions to not obviously support a single analysis? One particular approach from a naturalistic perspective treats this question from the point of view of the psychology of concepts. According to it, this failure is explained by the structure of our folk concept of knowledge, which organizes its constitutive information in a much looser way than we assume when we rely on intuitive knowledge ascriptions. I will adopt the same starting point here, but argue against the proposed answer and defend the view that this difficulty is explained not by something related to the specific structure of our concept of knowledge but, on the contrary, by its lack of structure. I claim that our folk concept of knowledge should be understood as a primitive mental state concept.Downloads
References
Aikhenvald, A. (2004). Evidentiality. New York, NY: Oxford UP.
Apperly, I. (2011). Mindreaders: The Cognitive Basis of “Theory of Mind”. Hove and New York: Psychology Press.
Baron & Cohen, S. (1994). The eye direction detector (EDD) and the shared attention mechanism (SAM): Two cases for evolutionary psychology. In C. Moore & P. Dunham (Eds.), The Role of Joint Attention in Development (pp. 41-59). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Bealer, G. (1998). Intuition and the Autonomy of Philosophy, In DePaul, M. and Ramsey, W. (eds.) Rethinking Intuition. Oxford: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc., 201-39.
Birch, S. & Bloom, P. (2007). The curse of knowledge in reasoning about false beliefs. Psychological Science, 18(5), 382–386.
Coleman, L., & Kay, S. (1981). Prototype semantics: The english word LIE. Language 57: 26-44.
Comesaña, J. (2005). Unsafe Knowledge. Synthese, 146(3): 395–404.
Davies, M. & Stone, T. (2001). Mental simulation, tacit theory, and the threat of collapse. Philosophical Topics, 29, 127–173.
De Villiers, J. (2007). The interface of language and Theory of Mind. Lingua, 117(11), 1858-1878.
Fischhoff, B. (1975). Hindsight ≠ foresight: The effect of outcome knowledge on judgment under uncertainty. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 1, 288-299
Fodor, J. (1998). There are no recognitional concepts – not even RED In In Critical Condition, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 35–47.
Frankish, K., & Evans, J. (2009). The duality of mind: an historical perspective. In K. Frankish & J. Evans (Eds.), In Two Minds: Dual Process Theory and Beyond (pp. 1–29). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gettier, E. (1963). Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Analysis, 23: 121-123.
Goldman, A. (1993). Epistemic Folkways and Scientific Epistemology. Philosophical Issues, 3, p. 271-285.
Goldman, A. (1995). In defense of the simulation theory. In M. Davies and T. Stone (eds.), Folk Psychology. Oxford, Blackwell, pp. 191–206.
Goldman, A. (2006). Simulating Minds. Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Goldman, A. (2007). Philosophical Intuitions: Their Target, Their Source, and Their Epistemic Status. Grazer Philosophische Studien 74: 1-26
Goldman, A., and Pust, J. (1998). Philosophical Theory and Intuitional Evidence, in M. DePaul and W. Ramsey, (eds), Rethinking Intuition: The Psychology of Intuition and Its Role in Philosophical Inquiry, 179-197, Rowman & Littlefield.
Hampton, J. (1981). An investigation of the nature of abstract concepts. Memory and Cognition 9 (2).
Hintikka, J. (1999). The Emperor’s New Intuitions. Journal of Philosophy 96(3), 127–147.
Kim, M., and Yuan, Y. (2015)._No Cross-Cultural Differences in the Gettier Car Case Intuition: A Replication Study of Weinberg Et Al. 2001. Episteme_12 (3):355-361.
Kim, M., and Yuan, Y. (Forthcoming) Cross-Cultural Universality of Knowledge Attributions.
Kornblith, H. (2002). Knowledge and Its Place in Nature. Oxford University Press.
Kornblith, H. (2007). Naturalism and Intuitions. Grazer Philosophische Studien 74, 27–49.
Laurence, S., & Margolis, E. (1999). Concepts and Cognitive Science, In E. Margolis & S. Laurence (eds.) Concepts: Core Readings (p. 3-81). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Nagel, J. (2010). Epistemic Anxiety and Adaptive Invariantism. Philosophical Perspectives 24, 407-435.
Nagel, J. (2012). Mindreading in Gettier Cases and Skeptical Pressure Cases. In Knowledge Ascription: New Essays, Jessica Brown and Mikkel Gerken, eds. (Oxford University Press, 2012), 171-191.
Nagel, J. (2013). Knowledge as a Mental State. Oxford Studies in Epistemology 4, 275-310.
Nagel, J., San Juan, V. & Mar, R. (2013). Lay Denial of Knowledge for Justified True Beliefs. Cognition, 129, p. 652-661.
Papafragou, A., Li, P., Choi, Y and Han, C. (2007). Evidentiality in Language and Cognition. Cognition 103: 253–99.
Piaget, J., & Inhelder, B. (1956). The child's conception of space. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Pollock, J. (1995). Cognitive Carpentry: A Blueprint for How to Build a Person. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Premack, D., Woodruff, G. (1978). Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind?. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 1 (4), 515–526.
Ramsey, W. (1992). Prototypes and Conceptual Analysis. Topoi 11:59–70.
Rosch, E. (1973). On the internal structure of perceptual and semantic categories. in Cognitive Development and the Acquisition of Language, T. E. Moore (ed.), Academic Press, New York.
Saxe, R. (2005). Against simulation: the argument from error. Trends in cognitive sciences, 9(4), 174-179.
Sosa, E. (2002). Tracking, Competence, and Knowledge. In P. Moser (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Schwanenflugel, P. (1991). Why are abstract concepts hard to understand? In Schwanenflugel, P. (ed), The psychology of word meanings. Hillsdale, NJ, Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, pp 223-250.
Tomasello, M., Call, J. (1997). Primate cognition. New York, NY, USA: Oxford University Press.
Turri, J. (2013). A conspicuous art: putting Gettier to the Test. Philosophers’ imprint, 13(10), 1–16._
Vogel, J. (1987). Tracking, Closure, and Inductive Knowledge. In S. Luper-Foy (ed.), The Possibility of Knowledge, Rowman and Littlefield.
Weinberg, J., Nichols, S. and Stich, S. (2001). Normativity and Epistemic Intuitions. Philosophical Topics, 29, 429-460.
Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its Limits. New York: Oxford University Press.
Wittgenstein, L. (1953/2001). Philosophical Investigations. Blackwell Publishing.
Zagzebski, L. (1994). The inescapability of Gettier problems. The Philosophical Quarterly, 44, 65–73.
Additional Files
Published
How to Cite
Issue
Section
License
Journal general policy
1.This journal works under a Creative Commons License aplied to online journals. That icence can be read in the following link: Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0).
2.Accordingly to this License, a)the journal declares that authors hold the copyright of their articles without restrictions, and they can archieve them as post-print elsewhere. b)the journal allow the author(s) to retain publishing rights without restrictions.
Metadata Policy for information describing items in the repository
1. Anyone may access the metadata free of charge at anytime.
2.The metadata may be re-used in any medium without prior permission, even commercial purposes provided the OAI Identifier or a link to the original metadata record are given, under the terms of a CC BY license refered for the Journal.